Welcome to Eureka Street

back to site

In an unjust world, can war ever be just?

 

In his paper, ‘All Things Considered: Making Moral Sense of the Wars in Ukraine and Gaza’, which he later discussed on the ABC Religion and Ethics Report, Nigel Biggar rightly says that Just War Theory is a good frame for thinking and arguing about the morality of war.  Christians, like everyone who wants to think ethically, struggle with questions about war.  On the one hand, we are called to be peacemakers, and the central figure of our tradition made no resistance to being unjustly tried, tortured and killed — in fact he criticised his own followers when they attempted to respond violently to his arrest.  On the other hand, many of us think that while it might be alright to be a pacifist when I am attacked (as Jesus seems to advocate), it might not be right for me to allow someone else — an innocent child, for example — to be unjustly harmed when I could do something about it.  When we magnify that concern to encompass an entire population or people group, we have the moral problem of war.

If we do not take a pacifist position, then it seems Christians have to do two things at once.  We have to look at other humans as sacred—as loved and held in existence by God who is the mysterious but loving energy that sustains the universe.  At the same time, we have to admit that under the right conditions, these very same humans may be legitimately shot, blown up, burned, injured to the point of unrecognisability, traumatised beyond measure, or killed.  It is no wonder that many Christians throughout history have taken this to be an impossible cognitive dissonance, and adopted a purely pacifist position.  It is also no wonder that for those of us who do not take the pacifist path, one of the criteria of ‘Just War Theory’ is that violence must be the absolute ‘last resort’.  If it is ever the case that we can legitimately commit or support the kinds of horrific violations of other human beings that occur in even the most just of wars, then we had better be sure that these actions are absolutely necessary.  Hence Just War Theory says that a war can be justified only if it has a just cause, if it is engaged in for the right reasons, if it is the last resort, if the violence is proportional to the ends to be achieved, and if it is waged by a legitimate authority.

Nigel Biggar describes Israel’s cause in the current war in Gaza as ‘taking military action to defend its people by rendering Hamas incapable of repeating what it did’.  What Hamas did was ‘the intentionally and sadistically indiscriminate slaughter of more than 1100 men, women, and children on October 7.’  Biggar claims that ‘in response to such an attack, Israel was fully justified in taking up arms to uproot its malevolent cause.’  It is worth noting that he makes slightly different claims here: ‘rendering Hamas incapable’ is not necessarily the same as ‘uprooting’ them.  But we will return to this later.

Biggar’s reasoning is that if Israel has a just cause, and if a certain violent set of actions is necessary to achieve that cause, then no secondary effect of that violence, foreseen or otherwise, can affect the moral character of what Israel does.  This is the so-called ‘doctrine of double effect’: ‘a single, deliberate action can have two effects or consequences, a good or permissible one that is intended, and a bad or impermissible one that is unintended but, tragically, unavoidable in the circumstances.’  Biggar concludes that:  ‘As for [Israel’s military action in] Gaza, notwithstanding the concerns by some over the convoluted origins of the State of Israel, I believe it to be legitimate.’

Biggar is right about the ‘sadistic and indiscriminate slaughter’ perpetrated by Hamas.  If in Australia we sometimes seem to spend a disproportionate amount of time discussing the ethics of Israel’s actions rather than those of Hamas, it might be partly because Hamas holds itself to no standard we can recognise. 

But it is worth noting that a cause can be good but not just.  To take a trivial example: it is good for me not to be late for my dental appointment.  If I am late I may inconvenience others and I may not get the dental care I need.  If, due to circumstances beyond my control, the only way I can avoid being late is to drive well over the speed limit and run every single red light between my house and the dentist’s, then the good cause of my being on time is not a just cause.  In fact I will have to forfeit this good cause because I cannot achieve it in a just way.  The means are not proportionate to my (entirely good) ends.

Biggar notes that this concept of proportionality ‘can mean several different things’ when we use it to think about whether to go to war.  It can mean that the benefits of going to war should exceed the costs; but Biggar thinks that ‘such a calculation is usually impossible.’  It can mean that fewer innocent people should be killed than the number we are trying to save; but Biggar notes that ‘the aim of a “just war” is seldom merely to save a certain number of lives, but to create new political conditions where the relevant grave injustice will cease and not easily recur to oppress future generations’ (he gives the example of the war against Hitler, which killed tens of millions of people yet is generally considered just).  Given the difficulties in saying what ‘proportionality’ means, Biggar suggests that we should simply ask whether war is ‘a necessary or the most apt means to achieve the goal of overcoming a grave injustice.’

But what does ‘most apt’ mean in this context?  When it comes to Gaza, Biggar notes that ‘appalling civilian suffering on a large scale’ is not in itself a sign that Israel has acted ‘disproportionately’; that is, beyond what is necessary to achieve their just cause.

 

'The evil done on October 7 was reprehensible, as is the reluctance of some in Australia to condemn it. Israel suffered a national trauma. It would be a good thing if Hamas did not exist. But this good cause is not a just cause if it cannot be achieved without perpetrating a greater evil than the one we are hoping to prevent.' 

 

Perhaps; but surely the ‘appalling civilian suffering’ that he is talking about here—men and women smashed to pieces, bodies torn apart by bombs, children bleeding to death in their parents’ arms—must inform our thinking about what is ‘apt’ to achieving even the most just of goals?  In describing the doctrine of double effect, Biggar says that ‘the desired consequence or effect is what we intend; the unwanted effect we accept with active reluctance.’  What does ‘active reluctance’ mean, if not a desperate effort to find a way to bring this ‘appalling civilian suffering’ to an end?

Surely one thing that our ‘active reluctance’ should do is prompt us to be relentlessly precise in determining exactly what cause might be considered just in this situation.  Israel’s leaders have stated that their goal is the complete destruction of Hamas.  We can understand why. The evil done on October 7 was reprehensible, as is the reluctance of some in Australia to condemn it. Israel suffered a national trauma. It would be a good thing if Hamas did not exist. But this good cause is not a just cause if it cannot be achieved without perpetrating a greater evil than the one we are hoping to prevent.  Biggar may rightly point out that such a calculation is impossible; but if this is the case, should the default response be violence or restraint? If there is a way of protecting Israel that falls short of the complete destruction of Hamas, then this may be the just cause we are looking for. Certainly a just response to October 7 can involve nothing more than the bare minimum required to reasonably ensure Israel’s security.

Biggar admits that ‘crushing Hamas’s military capability now, while necessary and right, is no complete, long-term solution to the running sore of Palestinian displacement.’  He goes on:  ‘It is a practical certainty that, in time, Hamas will rebuild itself, rearm, and strike again. And again. And again.’  If this is the case then the destruction of Hamas, being impossible, cannot justify Israel’s military action. To remove Hamas is a worthy goal. But not every worthy goal can be achieved in a just way. 

Many world leaders, including our own in Australia, have affirmed Israel’s right to defend itself. This is correct. Nigel Biggar has noted that this may come at a cost to civilians. This is also correct. But a Christian who understands every human being as loved by God, as well as anyone else who holds that every human being possesses an inviolable dignity, must insist that ‘appalling civilian suffering’ of the kind we are seeing in Gaza (and, for that matter, in Sudan and other places) is never in any final sense acceptable: at the very least, our ‘active reluctance’ must prompt us to insist that one power hold itself to Just War principles, even when the other power refuses to.

 

 


Daniel Nellor is Research Officer at The Wesley Centre for Theology, Ethics, and Public Policy. His latest book is What Are They Thinking? Conversations With Australian Philosophers (Australian Scholarly Publishing, 2023).

Topic tags: Daniel Nellor, War, Peace, Justice, Gaza

 

 

submit a comment

Existing comments

The Israel/Hamas conflict is, sadly, so entrenched and intractable. For Christians attempting to think and act in an ethical manner about this war there is the knowledge that Jesus was a Palestinian Jew. This brings the war in the Middle East very close. Israel has been traumatised by the 7 October attack and now Gaza is being traumatised by a retaliation born of fear and a perception by Israel of a fight for their very existence. It is difficult in the messiness of war to see perpetrators (on either side) as people loved by God. I’m unsure though that Israel can psychologically take this on board. There would be many people on both sides of the conflict who are desperate for peace. But that means both sides would need to see ‘the other’ and not necessarily framed as an exercise in an ethical dilemma.


Pam | 27 August 2024  

Nigel Biggar has been called wrong once on the application of his moral philosophy to colonialism by the respected historian Alan Lester, so I do not see him as infallible. Whether Jesus was a pacifist is, I think, both debatable, and, in this matter, a red herring. Jesus was not a violent revolutionary like the Zealots. To have violently opposed Roman authority in Palestine would have invoked a totally disproportionate response: just as Israel's response to the horrific murder of innocent civilians by Hamas can also be seen as disproportionate. A former British Army officer described the problem of Israel/Palestine as not a matter of right and wrong, but a matter of rights and rights. Hamas is not democratically elected in our sense and many Palestinians do not support it. To say so in Gaza would be extremely unwise. Where do we go from here? To get down to the nitty gritty of real peace in Israel/Palestine is a herculean task. I do not think it is assisted by Biggar's philosophizing. It needs a real change at the coalface. Will that come?


Edward Fido | 28 August 2024  

Jesus lived in a world much more unjust than, at least, the world of us in the First World, and did almost nothing with his divine power to ameliorate the injustices he saw around him for most of his life. (At least, the divine inspiration behind Scripture chooses not to report any miracles he may have worked before his commissioning as Saviour by the water baptism from John.) Of course, that must have been because he was following his father's will to focus on what the father decided should matter to him.

That opens up the logical possibility that it may be a greater good in this morally contingent and finite world to allow evils, even substantial ones, like tares, to flourish until they are weeded by God in his own time.

Leaving aside the pertinent point that the divine privilege of doing something in a particular way is not to be usurped by humans, in the same way that the Catholic Church teaches, unlike the Protestants, that as God desires to save everybody, the Church cannot preempt God by saying that salvation is possible only in one way (God being above his sacraments), it is possible that a properly modest theology of morality for a world bound by practical realities should accept as a principle that some unpleasant things should be allowed to reap their consequences because all unpleasant things do the greater job of proving the truth that human free will, in this world, is not perfect, not even good ("only God is good"), but permanently imperfect.

To decide what unpleasant events should be allowed to continue as evidence of the consequences of free will is, indeed, contestable. What is not contestable is that humans should not be so arrogant that they can come up with a perfect theology of how to remain with clean hands in a world bound by practical realities. A properly modest theology would have to say that on some occasions, no clean hands are possible because to say otherwise is to defy God to assert that it is possible to remain sinless in a sinful world. If that is the case, what is the role of Mercy?

A properly modest theology would accept the possibility that the greater morality is served by letting the bombardment of Gaza continue. Is that worse than the Babylonian Captivity?


roy chen yee | 28 August 2024  

If we're going to talk about just cause and the right to defend - do Hamas and the Palestinians have just cause to attack Israel for all they have endured for decades? Under that framing, I'd say yes. But that's been a recipe for unending violence.

I don't think looking back to history and justifying recriminations will take anyone towards peace. Peace has to be forward looking and to a large extent, past acts have to be forgiven.

The question is: do both sides want peace or mighty stories of vengeance and vanquishing the enemy?


Anne Marie | 29 August 2024  

Over time in the long debate over "just war", we have seen a slow steady lean toward the ideal that no war is just. Again, as an ideal, most would agree. We should also be aware though of the occurrence of "unjust peace". An example from our own region is the experience of Bougainville. Communities there lived with continued injustice, inequality and destruction of their land, resorting to conflict after peaceful avenues of negotiation were exhausted and their voices casually ignored.


Kevin Wilson | 30 August 2024  

This article gave me solace. Thank you


Aveen Stephenson | 30 August 2024